7 Comments
User's avatar
Williams's avatar

I am new to Austrian economics and I would love to know more about this so I would love if you could publish a article about basics

Expand full comment
dabchick's avatar

In my opinion, books are the gold standard for learning—the best one on Austrian economics is Per Bylund’s “How to Think About the Economy”, available for free here: https://mises.org/library/book/how-think-about-economy-primer

I may write more about the basics, but it’s difficult to do so in short form. This is the shortest primer out there, and it’s about a hundred pages!

Expand full comment
Craig Duddy's avatar

I think you slightly understate the core of the Hayekian Research paradigm here and are too quick to separate the Mises and Hayek positions. Each fall back on each other. I have no qualms with the Misesian position, but it’s been pretty characteristic for a while how understated the epistemic question is. The price system serves to disseminate asymmetric information, but more than that it is feedback and learning. It serves to signal tacit information, both inarticulate as the existing ‘stock’ and unknowable as a future ‘flow.’

Rational economic calculation is impossible due to this inability of the planner to acquire both instantaneously full information about objective detached facts, and knowledge that is subject dependent. We cannot make the ‘best use of alternative resources’ as there is no basis for assessing opportunity costs. These are fundamentally institutional, and knowledge questions. Exchanges serves to facilitate resources to actors themselves. Prices are not the fundamental, that comes down to people and exchange as James Buchanan has previously emphasised. The essence of coordination is—in my view—far more explicitly made in the work of Hayek than any other Austrian who came before it. This is made fairly obvious to me from the inspiration it took toward spontaneous order, in extending entrepreneurship to theory of institutions and the backdrop we need to produce growth. Prices fail if they produce wrong signals or incentives, and they fail if the costs of transacting is too high. The result of this is a vital transition into institutional theory, that allows investigation of knowledge more broadly in the social sciences and systems which go against the constructivist vision. They are systems of human action — and yet not systems of human design.

Expand full comment
dabchick's avatar

I don’t think the constructivist and institutional readings are necessarily opposed. The libertarian property theory is an indispensable starting point for the analysis, and the institutional analysis smooths out the “rough edge cases” imo. The institution of private property is both necessary and sufficient in order for rational economic calculation to take place, but the particular instantiations are of course important to study. My issue with the existing institutional approach is the lack of a firm starting point for the analysis—this gap is filled by the libertarian (Rothbard-Evers title-transfer) ethic.

Expand full comment
Craig Duddy's avatar

Assuming we’re using constructivism in the same sense, they’re not necessarily opposed in the same way as most debates — but there’s definitely important matters of emphasis. An interesting concept I read just the other day was the idea that a robust political economy has to start from the perspective of the bad case, I.e., assuming that property and exchange cannot be enforced. The problem in the constructivist view isn’t the institutions themselves, but there’s been a long neglected study of how we approach those institutions. Rules aren’t designed in full, but they’re a product of evolutionary frameworks, and yet not entirely detached from every subjects plans. I think that’s best reflected in constitutional theory. If rules aren’t exogenously given, but endogenously formed through a vast amount of inarticulate customs which it is the constitutions role to recognise and formalise, it becomes difficult to see how the constructivist vision of ‘designing’ order as a whole can be feasible.

You only really need to look to new development economics to see that we can’t start from the view we already have select institutions — because when we do there’s a major fallacy. We don’t take into account ‘stickiness’ and the enforcement costs of rules that don’t arise from the bottom-up. Many countries outside the west, particularly in agriculture had customs that somewhat resembled property rights, but when it was made explicit it was done so without recognition of vital aspects of ‘time and place’ knowledge of circumstance.

Constructivism has one part to play, but like Lavoie stressed, the relevant economic ‘calculus’ that both institutions themselves and in formalising rules must be concerned with is far beyond the scope of detached objective facts. I don’t view institutions as ‘smoothing out the edges’ as much as being vital to the entire system functioning as it should have. If people can’t exchange, or if there is no enforcement of contract, the whole apparatus fails. This is also true of economic calculation, if there is ‘prohibiters’ to the exchanges that would otherwise take place, information economies fail. Hayek noted this in The Use of Knowledge in Society, discussing the rigidity of prices and labour markets.

I do agree, though, that institutional theory was based too far in mainstream and social contract assumptions. I think there is an exchange paradigm of liberties, which perhaps needs to be integrated further into Rothbardian work as it tends to come off without degree.

Expand full comment
dabchick's avatar

Thought about this a lot—i think the constructivist can provide a plausible story of emergence by appealing to Ricardo’s theorem on comparative advantage. Mises for instance does this explicitly; he argues that the mutual recognition of gains from trade under the Division of Labour is the constitutive grounds for Civilisation to be MADE possible

Expand full comment
Craig Duddy's avatar

On an individual level, yes that’s true. Exchanges and the division labour take place because it’s a positive sum game between all participants, but when we deal with designating rules and order it goes beyond just rational design. It’s much like the market system — every individual ‘plans’ for their own goals and aims in the market, and by doing so it gives rise to an overall order that cannot be designed by anyone person. In institutions or rules, the story is much the same. People with fragmented knowledge of time and place, or different customs compete in an evolution to establish the most preferential rules, or institutions.

On an individual level, its people’s rational plans aiming at their own ends but on a larger economy/society level, it’s the classical problem of conflating individual action with collective action. Constructivism commits similar fallacies to that of the socialist planner, in that it assumes individuals in their limited and fragmented knowledge can design an overall order, but that isn’t quite true. They arise spontaneously, as a process of competition. It’s why we perhaps end up with more advantageous social relations in some communities to have communal ownership as opposed to formal private property etc, such as the Maasai in Kenya.

It’s primarily a matter of emphasis, but it’s an important one. Evolutionary ideas vs rationalist design seems insignificant until the logical dots are connected, and they become very big deals. Both institutions and rules are endogenous to society arising through a long time series of competition. People themselves don’t aim at designing an order — at least in the sense teleology would have it. It’s a catallaxy, with the individual plans giving rise to an order no one could have themselves designed.

This is perhaps a different scenario with constitutional design, though. It’s an interesting question about constitutional craftsmanship, and how it fits with the constructivist vision.

Expand full comment